Cogprints

MAKING SENSE OF CAUSAL INTERACTIONS BETWEEN CONSCIOUSNESS AND BRAIN

Velmans, Professor Max (2002) MAKING SENSE OF CAUSAL INTERACTIONS BETWEEN CONSCIOUSNESS AND BRAIN. [Journal (Paginated)]

Full text available as:

[img] HTML
176Kb

Abstract

My target article (henceforth referred to as TA) presents evidence for causal interactions between consciousness and brain and some standard ways of accounting for this evidence in clinical practice and neuropsychological theory. I also point out some of the problems of understanding such causal interactions that are not addressed by standard explanations. Most of the residual problems have to do with how to cross the “explanatory gap” from consciousness to brain. I then list some of the reasons why the route across this gap suggested by physicalism won't work, in spite of its current popularity in consciousness studies. My own suggested route across the explanatory gap is more subterranean, where consciousness and brain can be seen to be dual aspects of a unifying, psychophysical mind. Some of the steps on this deeper route still have to be filled in by empirical research. But (as far as I can judge) there are no gaps that cannot be filled—just a different way of understanding consciousness, mind, brain and their causal interaction, with some interesting consequences for our understanding of free will. The commentaries on TA examined many aspects of my thesis viewed from both Western and Eastern perspectives. This reply focuses on how dual-aspect monism compares with currently popular alternatives such as “nonreductive physicalism”, clarifies my own approach, and reconsiders how well this addresses the “hard” problems of consciousness. We re-examine how conscious experiences relate to their physical/functional correlates and whether useful analogies can be drawn with other, physical relationships that appear to have dual-aspects. We also examine some fundamental differences between Western and Eastern thought about whether the existence of the physical world or the existence of consciousness can be taken for granted (with consequential differences about which of these is “hard” to understand). I then suggest a form of dual-aspect Reflexive Monism that might provide a path between these ancient intellectual traditions that is consistent with science and with common sense.

Item Type:Journal (Paginated)
Additional Information:Reply to 8 commentaries in Special Issue of the Journal of Consciousness Studies
Keywords:consciousness, causality, brain, physicalism, dual-aspect theory, complementary perspectives, eastern philosophy, psychophysical, mind, reflexive monism, information, falsifiability
Subjects:Neuroscience > Neuropsychology
Psychology > Cognitive Psychology
Philosophy > Philosophy of Mind
ID Code:2751
Deposited By: Velmans, Professor Max,
Deposited On:31 Jan 2003
Last Modified:11 Mar 2011 08:55

References in Article

Select the SEEK icon to attempt to find the referenced article. If it does not appear to be in cogprints you will be forwarded to the paracite service. Poorly formated references will probably not work.

Arbuthnott, K.D. (1995), ‘Inhibitory mechanisms in cognition: Phenomena and models’, Cahiers de Psychologie Cognitive, 14(1), pp. 3-45.

Baars, B. J., Banks, W. P. and Newman, J. B. (2002) (eds.) Essential Sources in the Scientific Study of Consciousness. The MIT press. (in press)

Chalmers, A. F. (1992), What is this Thing Called Science? Open University Press.

John, E. R. (2002), ‘The neuropsychology of consciousness’, Brain Res Brain Res Rev, 39, pp. 1-28.

Kim, J. (1999), Mind in a Physical World, MIT Press.

Libet, B. (2003), ‘Can conscious experience affect brain activity? JCS (in press).

McFadden, J. (2002), ‘Synchronous firing and its influence on the brain’s electromagnetic field: Evidence for an electromagnetic theory of consciousness’, JCS, 9 (4), pp. 23-50.

McFadden, J. (2002), ‘The conscious electromagnetic information (Cemi) field theory: The hard problem made easy?’, JCS, 9 (8), pp. 45-60.

Melzack, R. (1987), ‘The short-form McGill Pain Questionnaire’, Pain, 30, pp. 191-197.

Metzinger, T. (2000) (ed.), Neural Correlates of Consciousness, The MIT Press.

Miller, G. A. (1956), ‘The magical number seven, plus or minus two: some limits of our capacity for processing information’, Psych Review, 63, pp. 81 – 97.

Perruchet & Vinter (2003), ‘The self-organizing consciousness’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences (in press)

Pockett, S. (2002), ‘Difficulties with the electromagnetic field theory of consciousness’, JCS, 9 (4), pp. 51-6.

Searle, J. (1990), ‘Consciousness, explanatory inversion and cognitive science’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13(4), pp. 585-642.

Thomson, E. (2001) (ed.), Between Ourselves: Second-Person Issues in the Study of Consciousness, Imprint Academic.

Varela, F. and Shear, J. (1999) (eds.), The View from Within: First person approaches to the study of consciousness, Imprint Academic.

Velmans, M. (1990), ‘Is the mind conscious, functional, or both?’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13, pp. 629-630.

Velmans, M. (1990a), ‘Consciousness, brain, and the physical world’, Philosophical Psychology, 3, pp. 77-99.

Velmans, M. (1991a), ‘Is human information processing conscious?’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14(4), pp. 651-701.

Velmans, M. (1999), ‘Intersubjective science’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(2/3), pp. 299-306.

Velmans, M. (1995), ‘The relation of consciousness to the material world’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), pp. 200-219.

Velmans, M. (2001), ‘Heterophenomenogy versus critical phenomenology: a dialogue with Dan Dennett’, http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00001795/index.html

Metadata

Repository Staff Only: item control page