Cogprints

HOW TO DEFINE CONSCIOUSNESS—AND HOW NOT TO DEFINE CONSCIOUSNESS

Velmans, Prof Max (2009) HOW TO DEFINE CONSCIOUSNESS—AND HOW NOT TO DEFINE CONSCIOUSNESS. [Journal (Paginated)]

Full text available as:

[img]
Preview
PDF - Accepted Version
200Kb

Abstract

Definitions of consciousness need to be sufficiently broad to include all examples of conscious states and sufficiently narrow to exclude entities, events and processes that are not conscious. Unfortunately, deviations from these simple principles are common in modern consciousness studies, with consequent confusion and internal division in the field. The present paper gives example of ways in which definitions of consciousness can be either too broad or too narrow. It also discusses some of the main ways in which pre-existing theoretical commitments (about the nature of consciousness, mind and world) have intruded into definitions. Similar problems can arise in the way a “conscious process” is defined, potentially obscuring the way that conscious phenomenology actually relates to its neural correlates and antecedent causes in the brain, body and external world. Once a definition of “consciousness” is firmly grounded in its phenomenology, investigations of its ontology and its relationships to entities, events and processes that are not conscious can begin, and this may in time transmute the meaning (or sense) of the term. As our scientific understanding of these relationships deepen, our understanding of what consciousness is will also deepen. A similar transmutation of meaning (with growth of knowledge) occurs with basic terms in physics such as "energy", and "time."

Item Type:Journal (Paginated)
Keywords:definition, consciousness, conscious process, unconscious, mind, phenomenology, access consciousness, global workspace
Subjects:Philosophy > Philosophy of Mind
Philosophy > Metaphysics
Psychology > Perceptual Cognitive Psychology
ID Code:6453
Deposited By: Velmans, Professor Max,
Deposited On:10 Jun 2009 07:59
Last Modified:11 Mar 2011 08:57

References in Article

Select the SEEK icon to attempt to find the referenced article. If it does not appear to be in cogprints you will be forwarded to the paracite service. Poorly formated references will probably not work.

Baars, B.J. (1988), A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness (New York: Cambridge University Press).

Baars, B.J. (1991), ‘A curious coincidence? Consciousness as an object of scientific scrutiny fits our personal experience remarkably well’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14(4), pp. 669-670.

Baars, B.J. (1994), ‘A thoroughly empirical approach to consciousness’, Psyche 1(6), http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v2/psyche-1-6-baars.html

Baars, B.J. (1997a), ‘Some essential differences between consciousness and attention, perception and working memory’, Consciousness and Cognition, 6 (2/3), pp. 363-371.

Baars, B.J. (1997b), ‘In the theatre of consciousness: global workspace theory, a rigorous scientific theory of consciousness’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4 (4), pp. 292-309.

Baars, B.J. (2007), ‘The global workspace theory of consciousness’, in M.Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 236-246.

Baars, B.J., Fehling, M.R., LaPolla, M. and McGovern, K. (1997), ‘Consciousness creates access: Conscious goal images recruit unconscious action routines, but goal competition serves to “liberate” such routines, causing predictable slips’, in J.D. Cohen and J.W. Schooler (eds.) Scientific Approaches to Consciousness (Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates), pp. 423-444.

Baars, B.J. and McGovern, K. (1996), ‘Cognitive views of consciousness: What are the facts? How can we explain them?’ in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews (London: Routledge), pp. 63-95.

Beenfeldt, C. (2008), ‘A philosophical critique of heterophenomenology’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15(8), pp. 5-34.

Block, N (1995), ‘On a confusion about a function of consciousness’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18(2), pp. 227-272.

Chalmers, D. (1995), ‘Facing up to the problem of consciousness’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), pp. 200-219.

Chalmers, D. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Crick, F. (1994), The Astonishing Hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul, (London: Simon & Schuster).

Dennett, D.C. (1991), Consciousness Explained, (London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press).

Dixon, N.F. (1981), Preconscious Processing, (Chichester: Wiley).

Dewey, J. (1991[1910]), How We Think, (Buffalo, NY: Prometheus).

Farthing, J.W. (1992), The Psychology of Consciousness, (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall).

Fontana, D. (2007), ‘Mystical experience’, in M. Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.) The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp 163-172.

Gallagher, D. (2007), ‘Phenomenological approaches to consciousness’, in M. Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.) The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp 686-696.

Goodale, M. A. and Milner, A. D. (2004), Sight Unseen: An Exploration of Conscious and Unconscious Vision (New York: Oxford University Press).

Jack, A. and Roepstorff, A. (eds.) (2003), Trusting the Subject? Volume 1: The Use of Introspective Evidence in Cognitive Science, (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic).

Jack, A and Roepstorff, A. (eds.) (2004), Trusting the Subject? Volume 2: The Use of Introspective Evidence in Cognitive Science, (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic).

Jeannerod, M. (2007), ‘Consciousness of action’, in M.Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 540-550.

Kihlstrom, J. F. (1987), ‘The cognitive unconscious’, Science, 237, pp. 1445-1452.

Kihlstrom, J. F., Dorfman, J. and Park, L. (2007), ‘Implicit and explicit memory and learning’, in M.Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 525-539.

Merikle, P. M. (2007), ‘Preconscious processing’, in M.Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 512-524.

Miller, G. (1962), The Science of Mental Life, (Gretna, LA: Pelican Books).

Reber, A. S. (1993), Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge: An Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious, (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

Searle, J. (2007), ‘Biological naturalism’, in M.Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 325-334.

Sen, S. (2008), ‘The Vedic-Upanisadic concept of Brahman (the highest God)’, in A. Eshleman (ed.) Readings in Philosophy of Religion: East Meets West, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 43-51.

Shear, J. (2007), ‘Eastern methods for investigating mind and consciousness’, in M. Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 697-710.

Shear, J. and Jevning, R. (1999), ‘Pure consciousness’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(2/3), pp. 189-213.

Sloman, A. (1991), ‘Developing concepts of consciousness’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14(4), pp. 694-695.

Sperry, R.W. (1969), ‘A modified concept of consciousness’, Psychological Review, 76(6), pp. 532-536.

Stanovich, K.E. (1991), ‘Damn! There goes that ghost again!’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14(4), pp. 696-697.

Varela, F. and Shear, J. (eds.) (1999), The View from Within: First person approaches to the study of consciousness, (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic).

Velmans, M. (1991a), ‘Is human information processing conscious?’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14(4), pp. 651-669.

Velmans, M. (1991b), ‘Consciousness from a first-person perspective’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14(4), pp. 702-726.

Velmans, M. (ed.) (1996), The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological and Clinical Reviews, (London: Routledge).

Velmans, M. (1998), ‘Goodbye to reductionism’, in S. Hameroff, A. Kaszniak and A. Scott (eds.), Towards a Science of Consciousness II: The Second Tucson Discussions and Debates, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

Velmans, M. (ed.) (2000), Investigating Phenomenal Consciousness: New Methodologies and Maps, (Amsterdam: John Benjamins).

Velmans, M. (2001), ‘Heterophenomenology versus critical phenomenology: A dialogue with Dan Dennett’, On-line debate at http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/17/95/index.html

Velmans, M. (2002), ‘How could conscious experiences affect brains?’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(11), pp. 3-29.

Velmans, M. (2007a), ‘Heterophenomenology versus critical phenomenology’, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, pp. 221-230.

Velmans, M. (2007b), ‘An epistemology for the study of consciousness’, in M.Velmans and S. Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness (Malden, MA: Blackwell), pp. 711-725.

Velmans, M. (2008), ‘Reflexive monism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15 (2), pp. 5-50.

Velmans, M. (2009), Understanding Consciousness, Edition 2, (London: Routledge/ Psychology Press).

Velmans, M. and Schneider, S. (eds.) (2007), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, (Malden, MA: Blackwell).

Wilson, T. D. (2002), Strangers to Ourselves: Discovering the Adaptive Unconscious, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).

Zahavi, D. (2007), ‘Killing the straw man: Dennett and phenomenology’, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), pp. 331-47.

Metadata

Repository Staff Only: item control page