WHY HUMAN GRANDMOTHERS MAY NEED LARGE BRAINS
Commentary on Skoyles on Brain-Expertise
Nicholas Humphrey
Centre for Philosophy of the Natural and Social Sciences
London School of Economics
Houghton Street
London, WC2A 2AE
United Kingdom
N.Humphrey@lse.ac.uk
Abstract
Skoyles's case against human brain size being related to IQ is strong; but his case in
favor of its being related to expertise is weak. I propose that the explanation for the
evolutionary expansion of the human brain in fact lies far away, in the need to have a
brain that could continue to function into old age.
1. Skoyles (1999) has presented a knock-down case that the evolutionary function of having
so large a brain as that of contemporary humans cannot be merely to boost general intelligence
as measured by IQ. In fact the evidence he reviews suggests that IQ asymptotes at a brain size
of around 750 cc, so that Homo erectus may have been every bit as clever by this measure as
we ourselves are. Why then should there have been the further enlargement of the brain in
evolution?
2. Skoyles reasonably argues that if the extra brain mass does not contribute to general
intelligence, it must contribute to something else that is evolutionarily advantageous. And his
favour ed candidate for this something else is expertise. Others, including myself, have made
alternative suggestions, such as that extra capacity is required for the development of
specialisms such as social skill, or language, or reflexive consciousness (reviewed in Mithen,
1994). Calvin, coming at the problem from a different angle, has proposed that a huge increase
in raw computing power was needed for humans to be able throw projectiles to hit small
targets (Calvin, 1983).
3. However, the evidence reviewed in this paper would seem to make trouble for every one of
these suggestions - including Skoyles's own. For what the case studies seem to show is that
individuals with very small brains can function more or less normally, not only on IQ tests, but
in every other important way as well. To be specific, when a man such as Daniel Lyon, with
half the normal brain mass, is described as having "nothing defective or peculiar about him,"
we should take it -- unless there is specific evidence to the contrary -- that not only is his
general intelligence in the normal range but so too is his social skill, language, consciousness,
and indeed his throwing skill. Skoyles would no doubt want to suggest that, even so, future
research may reveal that anyone with so small a brain would have to be lacking expertise. But
as yet, as I understand it, this suggestion remains pure hypothesis.
4. Extraordinary evidence perhaps requires extraordinary theoretical reorientation. Twenty
years ago there was an article in Science that described John Lorba's observations on
hydrocephalics who have severely depleted brain tissue, yet normal mental functioning. It was
titled "Is your brain really necessary?" (Lewin, 1980). For just the reasons Skoyles gives about
the survival costs of having a large brain, we can surely reject the idea that big brains really are
unnecessary -- in the sense that they bring no additional benefits whatever. Even so, perhaps
we should still entertain the possibility that, beyond a certain size, extra brain tissue really may
be effectively redundant. And yet there may still be a great advantage to possessing it, for a
different and surprising reason.
5. My own proposal, in short, is that the evolutionary advantage to modern humans of having
a large brain is that it helps us to live longer -- or, more specifically, that it helps to insure our
intellectual competence into an older old age.
6. The brain is of course a fragile organ, which is vulnerable not only to external knocks, and
internal hemorrhages and tumors, but also to intrinsic processes of cell death and decay. By
the time we reach middle age, the brains of every one of us will almost certainly have suffered
significant structural damage. Yet the fact is that the majority of us will not yet have suffered
any obvious intellectual loss. The reason is that, fortunately, we have more than enough brain
to make up for it.
7. Skoyles himself hints at this very point about the value of redundancy when he writes in
para. 30 that "the brain can easily recover from injuries incurred in small stages . . the brain
loss that occurs slowly can pass without notice. For example, asymptomatic meningioma can
grow (at an average of 2.4 millimeters a year) into the size of plums without noticeable
effect." My point is that the reason why the meningioma can grow so large without noticeable
effect is precisely because there is sufficient spare tissue to cover for whatever is being slowly
damaged.
8. Redundancy exists elsewhere in the human body, and the explanation may well be the same.
Consider for example the question of why we have two kidneys. The value of our having two
kidneys rather than one is not that this doubling-up allows us to perform excretory functions
differently or better. Rather it is that if and when something goes wrong with either one of the
kidneys, the other one can take over the whole job.
9. Someone born with only one working kidney could in fact expect to manage quite well for
many years. However, in the longer run he would be significantly more likely to die an early
death from renal failure. By the same token, perhaps, someone born with a Homo erectus
sized brain could expect to hold his own intellectually for thirty years or so. But in the longer
run he would be significantly more likely to die from brain failure.
10. How long did our Homo erectus ancestors typically live? There are no reliable estimates.
But it is clear from comparisons across the higher primates that life expectancy has in fact
increased progressively along the line that led to Homo sapiens (with chimpanzees for example
living twice as long as baboons, and contemporary humans living twice as long as
chimpanzees). A good guess would be that Homo erectus adults almost never lived beyond
forty years, being likely to die by that time from accident or disease, even if their brains were
still quite healthy.
11. This relatively short life-expectancy might explain why at that stage there would have been
little if any immediate selection pressure for an increase in brain size to provide spare capacity.
For, even though these Homo erectus individuals would arguably have run a high risk of dying
of brain failure if they had lived longer, the fact was they were almost all already dead by the
time these risks kicked in.
12. Modern humans, however, have evolved to have a considerably longer life-expectancy.
Indeed by 100,000 years ago, a good many adults were probably living into their sixties or
even seventies. Thus the selection pressure for developing a more redundant brain, capable of
recovering from damage, would have become much stronger. This could well have resulted in
the rapid doubling in brain size to the levels that are normal today.
13. The adaptive value of longer life -- especially a life that in women typically extends well
beyond the menopause -- is still not clear. But it is plausible to suppose that as human
survival became increasingly dependent on culturally acquired subsistence skills, and as social
life grew ever more complex, there would have been considerable advantage to families from
having living grandparents and even great-grandparents around (see Hawkes, 1997 ).
14. In sum, I suggest that small brained individuals, for all that they may have normal IQ and
indeed normal expertise, have seldom lived long enough to tell stories to their grandchildren.
So that evolution has passed them by.
REFERENCES
Calvin, W. H. (1983). A stone's throw and its launch window: timing precision and its
implications for language and hominid brains. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 104, 121-135.
Lewin, R. (1980). Is your brain really necessary? Science, 210, 1232-1234.
Hawkes. K. (1997). The grandmother hypothesis. Science, 25 April, 536.
Mithen, S. (1996). The Prehistory of the Mind. London: Thames and Hudson.
Skoyles, J. R. (1999). Human evolution expanded brains to increase expertise capacity, not IQ. PSYCHOLOQUY 10(2)