Cogprints

There is no Concrete (or: Living Within One's Means)

Harnad, Stevan (2003) There is no Concrete (or: Living Within One's Means). [Preprint]

Full text available as:

[img] HTML
67Kb

Abstract

We are accustomed to thinking that a primrose is "concrete" and a prime number is "abstract," that "roundness" is more abstract than "round," and that "property" is more abstract than "roundness." In reality, the relation between "abstract" and "concrete" is more like the (non)relation between "abstract" and "concave," "concrete" being a sensory term [about what something feels like] and "abstract" being a functional term (about what the sensorimotor system is doing with its input in order to produce its output): Feelings and things are correlated, but otherwise incommensurable. Everything that any sensorimotor system such as ourselves manages to categorize successfully is based on abstracting sensorimotor "affordances" (invariant features). The rest is merely a question of what inputs we can and do categorize, and what we must abstract from the particulars of each sensorimotor interaction in order to be able to categorize them correctly. To categorize, in other words, is to abstract. And not to categorize is merely to experience. Borges's Funes the Memorious, with his infinite, infallible rote memory, is a fictional hint at what it would be like not to be able to categorize, not to be able to selectively forget and ignore most of our input by abstracting only its reliably recurrent invariants. But a sensorimotor system like Funes would not really be viable, for if something along those lines did exist, it could not categorize recurrent objects, events or states, hence it could have no language, private or public, and could at most only feel, not function adaptively (hence survive). Luria's "S" in "The Mind of a Mnemonist" is a real-life approximation whose difficulties in conceptualizing were directly proportional to his difficulties in selectively forgetting and ignoring. Watanabe's "Ugly Duckling Theorem" shows how, if we did not selectively weight some properties more heavily than others, everything would be equally (and infinitely and indifferently) similar to everything else. Miller's "Magical Number Seven Plus or Minus Two" shows that there are (and must be) limitations on our capacity to process and remember information, both in our capacity to discriminate relatively (detect sameness/difference, degree-of-similarity) and in our capacity to discriminate absolutely (identify, categorize, name), The phenomenon of categorical perception shows how selective feature-detection puts a Whorfian "warp" on our feelings of similarity in the service of categorization, compressing within-category similarities and expanding between-category differences by abstracting and selectively filtering inputs through their invariant features, thereby allowing us to sort and name things reliably. Language does allow us to acquire categories indirectly through symbolic description ("hearsay," definition) instead of just through direct sensorimotor trial-and-error experience, but to do so, all the categories named and used in the description must be recursively grounded in direct sensorimotor invariants. Language is largely a way to ground new categories by recombining already grounded ones, often by making their implicit invariant features into explicit categories too. If prime numbers differ from primroses, it is hence only in the degree to which they happen to be indirect, explicit, language-mediated categories. Like everything else, they are recursively grounded in sensorimotor invariants. The democracy of things is that, for sensorimotor systems like ourselves, all things are just absolute discriminables: they number among those categories that our sensorimotor interactions can potentially afford, no more, no less. A primrose affords dicotyledonousness as reliably (if not as surely) as a numerosity of 6 (e.g., 6 primroses) affords factoring (whereas 7 does not).

Item Type:Preprint
Additional Information:Presented at conference on: "Access to the Abstract." University of Southern Denmark Odense, 30-31 May 2003. http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Temp/abstract.htm
Subjects:Computer Science > Robotics
ID Code:3024
Deposited By: Harnad, Stevan
Deposited On:19 Jun 2003
Last Modified:11 Mar 2011 08:55

References in Article

Select the SEEK icon to attempt to find the referenced article. If it does not appear to be in cogprints you will be forwarded to the paracite service. Poorly formated references will probably not work.

Biederman, I. & Shiffrar, M. M. (1987) Sexing day-old chicks: A case study and expert systems analysis of a difficult perceptual-learning task. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition 13: 640 - 645. http://www.phon.ucl.ac.uk/home/richardh/chicken.htm

Borges, J.L. (1962) Funes el memorioso

http://www.bridgewater.edu/~atrupe/GEC101/Funes.html

Cangelosi, A. & Harnad, S. (2001) The Adaptive Advantage of Symbolic Theft Over Sensorimotor Toil:Grounding Language in Perceptual Categories. Evolution of Communication 4(1) 117-142

http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/20/36/index.htm

Gibson, J.J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, Houghton Mifflin, Boston. (Currently published by Lawrence Eribaum, Hillsdale, NJ http://cognet.mit.edu/MITECS/Entry/gibson1

Harnad, S. (1987) Category Induction and Representation, Chapter 18 of: Harnad, S. (ed.) (1987) Categorical Perception: The Groundwork of Cognition . New York: Cambridge University Press.

http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/15/72/index.html

Harnad, S. (1990) The Symbol Grounding Problem Physica D 42: 335-346.

http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/06/15/index.html

Harnad, S. (2000) Minds, Machines, and Turing: The Indistinguishability of Indistinguishables. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 9(4): 425-445. (special issue on "Alan Turing and Artificial Intelligence")

http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/16/16/index.html

Harnad, S. (2001) No Easy Way Out. The Sciences 41(2) 36-42.

http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/16/23/index.html

Harnad, S. (2001) Harnad on Dennett on Chalmers on Consciousness: The Mind/Body Problem is the Feeling/Function Problem.

http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/21/30/index.html

Harnad, S. (2003) Can a Machine Be Conscious? How? Journal of Consciousness Studies (in press) http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Temp/machine.htm

Harnad, S. (2003) Categorical Perception. Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. Nature Publishing Group. Macmillan. http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Temp/catperc.html

Harnad, S. (2003) Symbol-Grounding Problem. Encylopedia of Cognitive Science. Nature Publishing Group. Macmillan. http://www.ecs.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/Temp/symgro.htm

Luria, A. R. (1968) The Mind of a Mnemonist. (Harvard University Press) http://qsilver.queensu.ca/~phil158a/memory/luria.htm

Miller, George (1956) The Magical Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two: Some Limits on Our Capacity for Processing Information. The Psychological Review 63:81-97 http://cogprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/archive/00000730/

Steklis, Horst Dieter and Harnad, Stevan (1976) From hand to mouth: Some critical stages in the evolution of language, In: Origins and Evolution of Language and Speech (Harnad, Stevan, Steklis , Horst Dieter and Lancaster, Jane B., Eds.), 445-455. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 280. http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/08/66/index.html

Watanabe, S., (1985)"Theorem of the Ugly Duckling", Pattern Recognition: Human and Mechanical, Wiley

http://www.kamalnigam.com/papers/thesis-nigam.pdf

Whorf, B.L. (1956) Language, Thought and Reality. (J.B. Carroll, Ed.) Cambridge: MIT http://www.mtsu.edu/~dlavery/Whorf/blwquotes.html

Metadata

Repository Staff Only: item control page