§1. Introduction
§2. Supposed Properties of Determination
§3. Determination, Supervenience, Explanation and Transitivity
§4. Determination, Supervenience, Identity and Asymmetry
§5. Determination and Ontological Primacy
1. Introduction
The answer, in a word, is No. Supervenience not asymmetric -- and neither is determination. This conclusion is of course radically at odds with conventional wisdom, intuition, and many very good philosophers. Hence explanations are in order, indeed at some length, and so too is the patience to follow them, step by step.
The first step is to recall that according to physicalism, the physical enjoys a fundamental ontological primacy over the nonphysical. In connection with this asymmetric primacy, physicalists assert not only the composition thesis that every concrete thing is composed solely of the basic physical entities, but also the determination thesis that the physical properties of things determine all their properties. As Jaegwon Kim says, "Any robust materialist position should affirm ... that what is material determines all that there is in the world."(1) Furthermore, according to Kim, the relevant relation of determinational dependence, which is a component of supervenience, is asymmetric: "Dependence, or determination, is usually understood to be asymmetric.... In most cases of interest supervenience seems in fact asymmetric."(2)
Kim's argument for this supposed asymmetry of the determination relation proves inconsistent with at least one further property he gives the relation, as we see in §§2-3. So too for supervenience. In particular, a premise of his argument conflicts with the relation's transitivity. Nor does the literature appear to contain any considerations congenial to physicalists that would negate transitivity in favor of Kim's argument for asymmetry. To the contrary, physicalists require the transitivity of determination/supervenience in order to marshal adequate empirical support for their claim that the physical determines/subvenes all there is in the world.
Worse, the supposed asymmetry of determination and supervenience proves inconsistent with any identity or equivalence between the nonphysical properties of a thing and its physical properties, according to §4. Because such identity and/or equivalence does hold for (at least) some non-physical properties, determination and supervenience are not asymmetric. Reductivists, therefore, including Kim, can ill afford either asymmetric determination or asymmetric supervenience. So too for eliminitivists, who require the higher-level properties that survive elimination to be identical with or at least (nomically) equivalent to physical properties. But even nonreductive physicalists will be sobered, if they expected determination and supervenience to be asymmetric, since they agree that some higher-level properties are indeed identical or at least equivalent to physical properties, just not all.
If determination and supervenience are not asymmetric, explications of them cannot be faulted for failing to entail asymmetry, as a number of them have been, whatever their other merits. This includes explications according to which determination and supervenience are nonreductive and/or "global."(3) On the other hand, anyone who rejects the asymmetry shoulders a twofold burden. Some explanation must be given of why the contrary intuition is so entrenched and widespread. And some explanation must be given of how the asymmetric ontological primacy of the physical is to be understood, if determination and supervenience are not asymmetric. The purpose of §5 is to provide the needed explanations.
This task is complicated by the tendency of different philosophers to understand "ontological primacy" in different ways, using the phrase in divergent unanalyzed senses. We need therefore to distinguish the main senses, in §5, and then, for each such sense, provide a positive account of the ontological primacy of the physical, and of the corresponding dependence of the nonphysical, according to which such primacy is asymmetric but determination and supervenience are not. Here I exploit neglected relations among determination/supervenience, explanation and the empirical evidence for the physical determination/supervenience of all that there is in the world. These relations enable us to understand why the intuition of asymmetry of determination and supervenience is so entrenched and widespread, as well as why the supposed asymmetry is not required by the ontological primacy of the physical.
2. Supposed properties of Determination
A relation is never asymmetric "absolutely" but only in a given set or field. For example, in the set of integers the relation "less than or equal to" is neither asymmetric nor symmetric; it is false that given any x and y in this set, if x is less than or equal to y, then y is not less than or equal to x, and false also that for any such x and y, if x is less than or equal to y, then y is less than or equal to x. But the relation "less than or equal to" is symmetric in a singleton set of integers, say {3}, since for any x and y in this set, if x is less than or equal to y, then y is less than or equal to x (that is, if 3 is less than or equal to 3, then 3 is less than or equal to 3).
Thus we need to be clear about the set or field in which the physicalist's determination relation is supposed to be asymmetric. Here we may follow Kim, who treats the relation as holding between properties from various sets of properties. For example, in a general claim of supervenience, as he calls it, the properties in "a given family of properties, say mental properties, supervene on [hence are determined by] another family, say neurobiological properties."(4) In this kind of case, the properties between which determination and/or supervenience holds form sets that amount to whole families of properties -- say the mental, the neurobiological, the physical.
But, as Kim says, physicalists need also to make specific claims of supervenience and/or determination. For example, they might claim that the specific property of being in pain supervenes on (hence is determined by) the activation of specified nerve fibers. In this kind of case, the properties between which determination and supervenience hold -- those of being in pain and of certain fibers' being activated -- form subsets (often singleton subsets) of whole families (the mental, the neurobiological). As Kim says, physicalists need to make these specific claims of determination in connection with explaining why the general claims hold and providing evidence for them.(5)
On this view, then, which is widespread, the field of the physicalist's relation of determinational dependence is the set of properties of things, both those properties that form whole families (the mental, the physical) and those from specific subsets of a family (say being in pain, certain fibers' being activated). But it will not matter for what follows whether the field is thought of in terms of properties, predicates, conditions, facts, phenomena, or states of affairs, all of which have their advocates. What will matter is that not only whole families of these but specific subsets of them are included in the field of the determination relation. So too for supervenience.
Let us follow Kim in a further particular as well. There is a difference between covariance and dependence, as there is between correlation and cause. A relation of covariance holds between properties of kind A and those of kind B when those in A covary, either "accidentally" or of necessity, with those in B. Specifically, we are only asserting covariance when we assert that there is no difference of sort A without a difference of sort B, or, modalizing, that difference in respect of A entails difference in respect of B. Dependence, on the other hand, requires more than covariance even when the covariance involves a strong modality.
For example, chemical kinds and their microphysical structures seem necessarily to covary with each other, in the sense that given identities like water = H2O, there can be no difference between two things in respect of the property of being water without some difference in respect of the property of being H2O, and vice versa (or, equivalently, any two worlds alike as regards which things have the property of being H2O are alike as regards which things have the property of being water, and vice versa). Thus the covariance in this kind of case appears not to be asymmetric. Yet we want to say that the chemical kind "water" is asymmetrically dependent on the microphysical structure H2O. Covariance can be non-asymmetric, whereas dependence seemingly cannot. Furthermore, questions of asymmetry aside, "it seems clearly possible for there to be three sets of properties A, B, and C, such that A and B depend on C, A covaries with B but B does not covary with A, and A does not depend on B."(6) This is largely because it could be in virtue of having certain properties in C, not B, that something has certain A-properties; it is the C-properties that play the relevant explanatory role.
In line with this distinction between covariance and dependence, we may again follow Kim, as we have been, in using the word 'determination' to mean not some variety of covariance but a kind of dependence. "For there to be property dependence there must be property covariation," but the converse does not hold, and "it is the dependence aspect of supervenience, not the covariation aspect, that can sanction many of the usual philosophical implications drawn from, or associated with, supervenience theses,"(7) including the asymmetric primacy of the physical.
What other properties should the physicalist's relation of determinational dependence have? According to Kim, the relation involves not only ontological directionality but explanatory. "That upon which something depends is ... explanatorily prior to ... that which depends on it." The lower-level or base property on which the higher-level depends is explanatorily prior because a thing's "having the relevant base property explains why it has the [higher-level] property." It is because, or in virtue of the fact that, the thing has the base property that it has the higher-level, supervenient property. Thus if properties of kind B determine those of kind A, then a thing's having certain B-properties is that in virtue of which, in the sense of explaining why, it has certain A-properties.(8)
Call this supposed feature of the determination relation that of implying an in-virtue-of or explanation relation. The in-virtue-of relation is implied in the sense that if the determination relation obtains between (sets of) properties F and G, so does the in-virtue-of or explanation relation: if F determines G, then a thing's having F explains its having G, and it is in virtue of having F that it has G. This feature of implying an in-virtue-of or explanation relation enables Kim's argument for the asymmetry of determination: The in-virtue-of or explanation relation is asymmetric, since if x's having F explains why x has G, then x's having G does not explain why x has F. Because this asymmetric relation is implied by the determination relation, the latter must be asymmetric too.(9)
Kim gives determination two further properties that will be relevant here. One is that "this
determinative relation [say from body to mind] is an objective matter; it does not depend on
whether anyone knows anything about it, or what expressions are used to talk about mind and
body."(10) This suggests that the relation is
extensional, since a mark of the extensional is that
the
relation obtains (or not) regardless of what expressions are used to talk about or denote its relata.
In any event, "supervenient determination ... is a metaphysical thesis about an objectively
existent dependency relation between the two domains; it says nothing about whether or how the
details of the dependency relation will become known so as to enable us to formulate
explanations, reductions, or definitions."(11) In
line with this, let us say that the physicalist's
determination relation has the property of being "objective," whether or not it is also
extensional.
Another property Kim gives determination is transitivity. Determination is a component of,
or implied by, supervenience, in the sense of supervenience that include dependence.(12) But
"Supervenience, whether in the sense of covariation or in the sense that includes dependence, is
transitive."(13) It follows that determination is
transitive too (for the relevant cases, in which there
are
Furthermore, as Kim himself might add, without this transitivity of determination, physicalists would be unable to marshal adequate empirical support for their claim that the higher-level scientific facts are determined ultimately by the physical facts. To see why, consider the claim that the physical facts determine the facts at the level of psychology.(14) A natural way to justify this claim empirically -- perhaps the only way -- is to look at a number of sciences between physics and psychology. The facts of physics can more readily be shown to determine those of its near neighbors, such as quantum chemistry. The latter can more readily be shown to determine the facts in sciences a bit further removed from physics, such as biochemistry. These in turn can more easily be seen to determine those in sciences still further removed, and so on, until finally we reach the psychological facts. Provided determination holds at each step of the way in this chain, we may infer by transitivity of determination that the physical facts determine the psychological.
Sometimes, of course, the higher-level phenomena are determined (and explained) not by matters in a single lower-level science but only in a cluster of lower-level sciences, in each of which the facts are determined (and explained) in turn by some closer still to physics. What get pairwise connected at each step, strictly, include such clusters of sciences, not always single sciences.(15) But for simplicity let us continue to speak as though it is single sciences that get pairwise connected and form chains.
For in any event, the problem of providing adequate
empirical evidence for the determination of
the psychological by the physical divides into a number of intermediate problems that concern
relations between sciences that are near neighbors. Scientists in a couple of neighboring fields
will often already have explored key relations between them, including evidential relations in
light of which we may infer determination of one by the other. This amounts to a division of
labor, in which physicalists can let the particular sciences do much of their work for them. If
determination were not transitive, this division of labor would be of no use to physicalists who
want to marshal adequate empirical support for the claim that the psychological facts are
determined ultimately by the physical facts. Without transitivity of determination, physicalists
would have to shoulder the heroic and probably hopeless burden of spelling out some
direct or
unmediated connection between psychology and physics -- a connection that would
leapfrog the
intervening sciences and enable us to infer determination of psychological fact by physical. The
prospects of some such leapfrog approach should strike us as dim (as we see in detail in the next
section, in connection with interlevel theories).(16)
Summing up, the properties Kim ascribes to the
physicalist's determination relation include the
following. The field of the relation (and also of supervenience) consists of properties, both those
that form whole families and those that form specific subsets of them. The relation is both
objective and a relation not merely of covariance but of directional dependence, having an
asymmetry derived from an implied in-virtue-of or explanation relation. But the conjunction of
these supposed properties of determination, as we see next, proves inconsistent with the
transitivity Kim also assumes and physicalists require. So too for supervenience, insofar as
supervenience shares these properties.
3. Determination, Supervenience, Explanation
and Transitivity
For simplicity, we start with determination. The
argument of this section will then apply,
essentially unchanged, to supervenience, insofar as supervenience shares the relevant
properties.
Suppose determination has an asymmetry that derives
from an implied in-virtue-of or
explanation relation. That is, if F determines G, it is asymmetrically
in virtue of, hence
explained by, having F that something has G (for any F
and G in the field of the determination
relation). It can be proved that for any relation R, if (i) R implies relation Q (in the sense that for
any Since there are cases in which D To see why the relevant kinds of explanation are not transitive, note to begin with that the
relevant kinds are "interlevel" explanations, in which some higher-level property N
is supposed to be explained by some lower-level properties Bi. Now
consider the following kind of interlevel explanation. Often we want to say both that in some
sense the best explanation of why x has N is that
x has Bi and that Bi determine
that x has N, where the properties Biare from
some science more fundamental, or closer to physics, than the science from which N
is drawn. Given the unifying and explanatory role of the more fundamental properties or
phenomena Bi (among other things), an interlevel explanation in terms
of Bi For example, there are occasions or contexts in
which, at least from the point of view of the
physicalist, (i) not only is the best explanation of why a certain cell x has the
biological property
N
that the cell has certain biochemical properties Bi Perhaps the moral here is simply that the relevant
notion of interlevel explanation involved in the
implied explanation relation is never that of the best explanation. But this move
would come at
too high a price. When physicalists say that x's having N is
determined by and thus had in virtue
of the more fundamental properties Bi According to some varieties, the explaining factors
merely make it sufficiently probable that x
has N. Among these varieties are deductive-statistical, inductive-statistical and
certain statistical-relevance explanations. Such varieties of explanation become relevant when
the lower-level Bi Perhaps the moral here is that an implied in-virtue-of
or explanation relation can be transitive
only if the properties in virtue of which x has a certain chance of having
N do not explain why x
has N by way of making it sufficiently probable that x has
N (unless we set the probability at
1). But again the price is too high. There are important interlevel explanations that are both
statistical or probabilistic in character and relevant when lower-level properties determine the
chances of x's having N. Such explanations are involved in, among
others, meteorology, the
social sciences, and population genetics. And of course physics itself is no stranger to the
statistical and the probabilistic.
Perhaps, however, there is some other relevant kind
of interlevel explanation that is transitive,
neither best explanation nor probabilifying explanation. It would seem not. Consider to begin
with the interlevel explanation of temperature in terms of mean molecular kinetic energy.
Strictly speaking, the bare physical fact that the molecules in my coffee have a certain mean
kinetic energy does not by itself explain, because it does not itself imply, that the coffee is piping
hot. What is required in addition is some correspondence rule or bridge principle that connects
mean molecular kinetic energy with temperature. Likewise, the bare physical fact that certain
protein molecules on a cell's surface have bonded to certain other molecules does not itself
explain, because it does not itself imply, that there has been communication of significant
biological information to the cell from its environment. We need an appropriate correspondence
rule or bridge principle connecting the two, if we want the assertion of interlevel explanation
actually to be an explanation or to explain.
What this suggests is that an assertion to the effect that the lower-level properties
Bi explain the higher-level N is elliptical. What is called
interlevel explanation of N by Bi is typically
explanation of N by Bi within or relative to an interlevel
theory. For it is only within interlevel theories that we find the appropriate bridge principles,
those that enable us to connect Bi with N so as to warrant
the elliptical assertion that N is explained by
Bi. What
explains N, more strictly,
is the conjunction of Bi Even the latter assertion is somewhat elliptical, since
what the relevant principle is and just how
it is to be interpreted and applied depend on the theory. So we should say that what explains
N,
strictly, are Bi
conjoined with a bridge principle within a specified interlevel theory T. For
example, it is only within the interlevel theory we call a kinetic theory of temperature, and given
the appropriate bridge principle it contains, that my coffee's being hot has an interlevel
explanation in terms of the mean kinetic energy of its molecules. Likewise, it is only within a
molecular biology that cell communication has an interlevel explanation in terms of the
biochemical properties of certain molecules. Interlevel explanations ride on interlevel
theories.
Whether and in what sense an interlevel explanation
is an explanation or does explain, and to
what extent it is or does, obviously depend heavily on whether and to what extent the relevant
interlevel theory satisfies certain conditions. This in turn is mostly a matter of how successful
the interlevel theory is in connecting a higher-level theory T2 (say, cell biology)
with a lower-level theory T1 (say, biochemistry). The most successful interlevel
theories are those that among
other things effect the greatest degree of "unification" of T1 and T2
(as in the case of molecular
biology). Such interlevel theories involve at least the following sorts of connections between
T1
and T2:(21)
(1) The ontology of T1 exhausts that of T2 (by way of
every object described by T2 being composed of or token-identical with an object or
sum of objects described by T1).
(2) T1 and T2 are logically compatible.
(3) The referents of the basic predicates of T1 determine those of
T2.
(4) We can say how it is that (3) holds.
(5) T1 and T2 are heuristically dependent on each other --
each uses the other to suggest fruitful lines of research.
(6) T1 and T2 are confirmationally dependent on each
other --each uses the other in the design of experimental tests.
(7) Each uses, explicitly or implicitly, explanations from the other.
When we study the standards actually used for
evaluating how successful a scientific interlevel
theory is, (1)-(7) are among those (implicitly) used by scientists engaged in evaluating (and
constructing) interlevel theories (physical chemistry, molecular biology, physiological
psychology, and so on). Conditions (5)-(7) are generally of more concern to such scientists than
(1)-(4), which may be of more concern to philosophers. In any event, an interlevel explanation is
an explanation, or explains, only in the sense that, or to the extent that, (1)-(7) are satisfied by the
interlevel theory on which it is parasitic.
Now consider a chain of interlevel explanations. In
particular, consider one in which there is (i)
an interlevel explanation of a cell-biological property N by biochemical properties
Bi; (ii) an
interlevel explanation, in the same sense or to the same extent, of
Bi by
quantum-chemical
properties Ci; and
(iii) an interlevel explanation, again in the same sense or to the same extent, of
Ci by
quantum-physical properties Pi
Suppose, then, that any interlevel explanation in the chain is an explanation only in the sense that, or to the same extent that, (1)-(7) are satisfied by the interlevel theory on which it is parasitic. It follows that if transitivity held for interlevel explanation, there would have to be an interlevel theory connecting quantum physics directly with cell biology, which theory satisfies (1)-(7) to the same extent as do the other interlevel theories on which the interlevel explanations in the chain are parasitic. So far as I know, there exists no such leapfrog interlevel theory, no such quantum-physical cell biology (as opposed to quantum-physical theories possibly of quite narrow subfields of cell biology). But let us waive the objection that no such theory exists, and assume for the sake of argument that it is at least possible in principle for an interlevel theory to be constructed that leapfrogs all the way from quantum physics to cell biology. The crucial question then is whether or to what extent this leapfrog theory would satisfy (1)-(7).
Suppose we grant that this leapfrog quantum-physical cell biology would satisfy (1) and (2), and grant further, at least for the sake of argument, that it would satisfy (3) and (4) to the same extent as do the other interlevel theories in the chain. That is, the ontology of quantum physics would exhaust that of cell biology; quantum physics and cell biology would be logically compatible; the referents of the basic quantum-physical predicates would determine those of the cell-biological predicates; and we could even say how this comes about.
What of (5)? Would quantum physics and cell biology be as heuristically dependent on each other as are such near neighbors as cell biology and biochemistry, biochemistry and quantum chemistry, quantum chemistry and quantum physics? Probably not. What of (6)? Would quantum physics and cell biology be as confirmationally dependent on each other as are such near neighbors as cell biology and biochemistry, biochemistry and quantum chemistry, quantum chemistry and quantum physics? Probably not. What of (7)? Would quantum physics and cell biology use explanations from each other to the degree characteristic of cell biology and biochemistry, biochemistry and quantum chemistry, and quantum chemistry and quantum physics? Probably not.
Note also that the issue of whether and to what extent
a leapfrog quantum-physical cell biology
would satisfy (5)-(7) is largely an empirical issue, which can only be
judged by (i) looking at the
characteristics of the relevant theories -- quantum physics, quantum chemistry, biochemistry, cell
biology -- as they have actually been developed so far by working scientists; and (ii) in light of
these characteristics, appraising the promise or otherwise of suitable interconnections among
them -- interconnections that would support the judgment that the leapfrog theory satisfies (5)-(7)
as well as do molecular biology and the other interlevel theories involved in this
chain.
True, it is not impossible that some day some
leapfrog quantum-physical cell biology could be
developed that satisfies (5)-(7) to the same extent as molecular biology and the other interlevel
theories in the chain. But it is improbable. And even if by chance some such leapfrog did
appear, there are other and much longer chains of interlevel explanations and theories we would
need to consider, stretching from physics to psychology, linguistics, semantics, and
anthropology, among others. How likely is it that there could be an interlevel theory that (i)
leapfrogs all the way from physics to linguistics, and (ii) connects the two so that they are as
heuristically, confirmationally and explanatorily interdependent as quantum physics and
quantum chemistry, or biochemistry and cell biology?
It looks as though interlevel explanation is not
transitive.(22) So too, therefore, for the needed
interlevel in-virtue-of or explanation relation. Note also that according to physicalists, each level
G in the chain determines the phenomena at the next higher level
G, all the way up. Hence we
have a situation in which there are F,G and
H such that DFG and
DGH but
not VFH
(where V is
the interlevel in-virtue-of or explanation relation at work here).
The result of trying to save the supposed asymmetry
of determination by appealing to an implied
interlevel in-virtue-of or explanation relation is non-transitivity of determination. Nor are we
free to conclude, "So much the worse for transitivity." Rejecting transitivity of determination
would deprive physicalists of the division of labor, noted in §2, that is necessary for marshaling
adequate evidential support for their claim that the physical determines everything nonphysical.
Otherwise physicalists would have to establish some direct, leapfrog connection between physics
and psychology, physics and anthropology, physics and linguistics, from which we could infer
that the physical determines the psychological, the anthropological, the linguistic.
So far in this section we have been talking about
determination. But we could equally well have
been talking about supervenience, insofar as supervenience shares the relevant properties with
determination. Simply replace each occurrence of the term 'determination' (or one of its
cognates) throughout the argument so far with an occurrence of 'supervenience' (or one of its
cognates), and the argument will apply to supervenience as well as to determination. The result
of trying to save the supposed asymmetry of supervenience by appealing to an implied interlevel
in-virtue-of or explanation relation is non-transitivity of supervenience, which is inconsistent
with the transitivity required for marshaling adequate evidential support for the physicalist's
claim that everything nonphysical supervenes on the physical.
Even though the argument of this section shows how
an asymmetry that derives from an implied
explanation relation is incompatible with the transitivity of determination and of supervenience,
of course it does not show that asymmetry as such is incompatible with transitivity. The alleged
asymmetry of the physicalist's determination and supervenience relations could derive from
something other than an implied explanation relation. On the other hand, the literature seems to
contain no other derivation of or argument for the alleged asymmetry. Rather than argument,
what one finds are appeals to intuition, to what physicalists seem to have in mind, or to some
general similarity between determination/supervenience and various relations held to be
asymmetric.(23)
Occasionally, however, something like the following
argument, often heard in conversation, may
lie tacitly in the background: Physicalists want to say that the physical determines the
mental but
the mental does not determine the physical; so the determination relation must be asymmetric; so
too for supervenience. But consider a parallel argument: We want to say that the set E
of even
integers is a subset of the set J of integers, but J is not a subset of E; so the subset relation must
be asymmetric. The premise here is true but the conclusion false; there are sets that are subsets
of each other. The tacit argument, interpreted this way, rests on a non
sequitur.
Perhaps instead the tacit argument is this: For each family G of
properties other than the physical, the physical determines every property in G, but
no property in G determines the physical; therefore, the determination relation is
asymmetric; so too for supervenience. This too fails. Compare: For each family
G of positive integers n other than 1, 1 is less than or equal to every
n in G, but no n in G is less than or equal to 1;
therefore, the less-than-or-equal-to relation is asymmetric. True premise, false conclusion.
One can imagine a further argument that begins by reminding us of the distinction between
covariance and dependence. Since we are talking of determinational dependence, not covariance,
and since dependence is an asymmetric relation, so therefore is determination. A serious
problem with this line is that not all varieties of dependence are asymmetric; the two halves of a
free-standing stone arch, for example, depend on each other to stay up -- a case of
co-dependence. Unless we are told more about the intended variety of dependence and just how
it differs from dependence in the stone-arch case Talk of dependence brings us to a related argument, or set of considerations, typically tacit,
to the effect the non-physical depends on the physical -- that the physical enjoys a certain priority
or primacy over the nonphysical, a priority that consists largely in the fact that the physical
determines the nonphysical but not vice versa; therefore, the determination relation is
asymmetric. But compare: the number 1 enjoys a certain priority over the other positive
integers n (it is, after all, the first), a priority which consists in large part in the fact
that 1 is less than or equal to n but n is not less than or equal to 1 for
each n other than 1; therefore, the less-than-or-equal-to relation is asymmetric. True
premise, false conclusion.
Of course there might be a kind of priority of the
physical over the nonphysical which, when
conjoined with further matters, entails that determination and/or supervenience should be
asymmetric. But we are told nothing about just what this kind of priority is and how it is
supposed to entail the would-be asymmetry. If, as is often the case, the priority is presumed to
derive from an implied in-virtue-of or explanation relation, it is incompatible with the required
transitivity of determination/supervenience, as seen. Whether there is some still further brand of
priority that entails asymmetry seems not to have been addressed. In any case, in §5 we return to
this matter of priority, and in particular to whether the ontological priority of the physical entails
asymmetry of determination or of supervenience. Meanwhile, instead of examining further
arguments for the asymmetry of determination and/or supervenience, let us consider an argument
4. Determination, Supervenience, Identity and
Asymmetry
The following example of a specific determination
claim serves to introduce a further property of
the physicalist's determination relation, one so far unremarked. The mean kinetic energy of the
molecules in my coffee, let us suppose, is what specifically determines the coffee's temperature.
But kinetic energy = 1/2mv2 What about substitutivity for the object place?
Suppose that certain biochemical properties Bi Pain may or may not be type-identical with certain
nerve fibers' being activated. But in other
cases it sometimes does happen not only that a higher-level property N is
determined by and/or
supervenes on a specific few lower-level properties
Bi In cases of this kind, since N is
determined by and/or supervenes on KBi Thus it seems that reductive physicalists, Kim
included, can ill afford to endorse asymmetry
either of determination or of supervenience. So too for eliminitivists, who require the
higher-level properties that survive elimination to be reducible to physical properties by way of
identity
or of equivalence. But the same is true even of nonreductive physicalists, since they agree that
some higher-level properties, just not all, are either identical with or equivalent to conjunctions
of physical properties.
This result -- that physicalist determination and supervenience are not asymmetric -- is so
counter-intuitive that many philosophers will insist there must be something seriously wrong
with the foregoing "substitutivity argument." Some might insist, for example, that the moral to
be drawn from the argument is merely that the determination relation is
anti-symmetric: for any F and G in its field, if it is
not the case that F=G, then if F determines G,
G does not determine F; so too for supervenience. The trouble with this
move -- aside from being ad hoc -- is that property equivalence does not guarantee property
identity, and there are cases in which it is not the case that F=G but
F is (nomologically) equivalent to G and it is by way of this equivalence
that F determines/subvenes G. In cases of this kind, it is not the case
that F=G, F determines/subvenes G, and, by
substitutivity of equivalents, G is determines/subvenes F.
Anti-symmetry fails as well.
Someone might instead object(26)
that if cases of identity really did pose this problem for the
supposed asymmetric determination/supervenience, such cases would pose a parallel problem for
asymmetric explanation and explanatory priority; and since explanation and explanatory priority
are certainly asymmetric, this reduces the foregoing substitutivity argument to absurdity. The
trouble with this objection is that there is no parallel problem for explanation, because
substitutivity fails for the relevant relations of explanation; we cannot infer from 'B
explains N'
and 'N = B' to 'N explains B'. For
suppose that a higher-level N is explained by a lower-level B
(or that having N is explained by having B), in the sense that
B, conjoined with the
correspondence rules or bridge principles in some empirically adequate interlevel theory
T,
nomologically implies N. In this case, B explains N but
N does not explain B; in view of the role
B plays in T (or in our use of T), B is
asymmetrically explanatorily prior to N. This asymmetry
holds even when the bridge principles in T happen to entail identity between
N and B, as many
think happens in a kinetic theory of temperature, so that temperature = mean molecular kinetic
energy. In such a theory (or our use of it), mean molecular kinetic energy is what explains
temperature, not vice versa, even though temperature = mean molecular kinetic energy; despite
the identity, temperature does not play the same role in the interlevel theory (or our use of it) as
does mean molecular kinetic energy. Thus we cannot infer from 'B explains
N' and 'N = B' to
'N explains B'; substitutivity of identity does not hold for
'F explains G' or for 'F is
explanatorily prior to G'.
Despite all this, suppose we were to ban substitutivity
for determination and supervenience, and
thus go non-extensional. Suppose in particular that someone could characterize an appropriate
interlevel determination/supervenience relation that is non-extensional in such a way as to block
substitutivity.
This would protect asymmetry from the substitutivity
argument, but at too high a price. One of
the physicalist's characteristic ontological theses, at the heart of physicalism, is that all the
phenomena are determined/supervenient on the physical phenomena. And as Kim says (noted in
§4), physicalist supervenient determination is an objective affair. Reality is so arranged, it
happens, that as a matter of objective fact, independent of our evidential and explanatory
schemes, and independent of what expressions are used to talk about things in reality, how the
things are as regards their non-physical properties is determined by and/or supervenient on how
things are as regards physical properties. If 'determine' and 'supervenes' were non-extensional
in the sense contemplated by those who would ban substitutivity, then the very formulation of
this objective ontological component of physicalism would involve a violation of the
extensionality that physicalists require, at least as an ideal, both in the language of physics and in
the terms they use to express their ontological position.
This extensionalist ideal does not imply
that the languages of higher-level theories -- psychology
or semantics, for example -- must be extensional, or even that they must be reducible to the
extensional. It implies only that the physical determination/supervenience of the higher-level
intensional affairs be compatible with the extensionality physicalists want at least at the level of
physics. In particular, the matter of which sentences at the level of psychology or semantics are
true, even when those sentences themselves contain an intensional idiom, is determined
by/supervenient on the physical phenomena extensionally construed. Any such account of
intensionality in terms of physical determination/supervenience would fail if the very
determination/supervenience relation presupposed were itself to harbor the intensionality that
was to be accounted for. A physicalist who would advocate intensionality of determination and
supervenience in order to defend their supposed asymmetry would manifest curious
priorities.
5. Determination and Ontological Primacy
If the physicalist's relations of determination and
supervenience are non-asymmetric, why is the
contrary intuition so entrenched and widespread? And without their asymmetry, how are we to
understand the asymmetric ontological primacy of the physical? Any answer is complicated by
the tendency of different philosophers to mean different things by "ontological primacy."
According to some, ontological primacy involves explanatory primacy: if F
is
ontologically prior
to G, then F is explanatorily prior to G. So let us begin
with explanatory primacy, returning
eventually to other things that might be meant by "ontological primacy."
It is illuminating to reflect yet again on the case in
which both F = G and it is by way of this
identity that F determines G. In this kind of case, it is especially
clear that a bare assertion of
determination does not, by itself, entail any kind of asymmetric primacy. For if F
determines G,
and F = G, then, in view of substitutivity, G determines
F just as much as F determines G; so too
for supervenience. Here there is no directionality or priority. And yet when physicalists assert,
as many do, that the property of being a middle-A sound is identical with and therefore is
determined/supervenient on a 440-Hz oscillation in air pressure, it is the latter that is supposed to
be prior, in some sense, to the former.
What sort of priority or primacy is this, and what is
its source, if not asymmetry of
determination/supervenience? The assumed identity connection between certain higher-level
properties and the lower-level properties suggests there might be a correspondence rule or bridge
principle nearby. And indeed when we inquire what evidence there is for the claim
that the two
kinds of property are related by identity, we soon encounter not only observed correlations
between them but prominent interlevel theories, such as a kinetic theory of temperature or a
molecular theory of water. The relevant bridge principles in the kinetic theory either take the
form of, or else support or warrant, assertions of identity between temperature and mean
molecular kinetic energy (or so it has been widely assumed).
Clearly, a crucial kind of evidence for an assertion of
interlevel identity is an empirically
adequate interlevel theory whose bridge principles support the assertion. But interlevel theories
are also designed to explain. Among other things, they are designed to explain the
higher-level
properties in terms of the lower-level. Such theories therefore involve explanatory directionality
or primacy -- an asymmetry whose source is not the bridge principles, since they are often
two-way conditionals or even identity statements or (other) statements of 1-1 correlations, but
elsewhere, perhaps not (explicitly) in the theory itself or in its logical form, but outside the
theory, whether in certain causal relations it may express or the use we make of it.
Now suppose that a higher-level property
N proves identical with some lower-level property P.
Identity, being symmetric, by itself entails no primacy. Nevertheless, the lower-level
P is
explanatorily prior to N by virtue of the role P plays in the relevant
interlevel theory (or our use
of it). Identity is symmetric, and yet when physicalists assert that temperature is identical with
mean molecular kinetic energy, it is the latter that takes priority, thanks to the explanatory
directionality of the interlevel theory on which the identity assertion is epistemically dependent
or parasitic. The priority involved is explanatory priority, and its source is an interlevel theory.
(The situation in which there is no interlevel theory on which the identity assertion could be
epistemically parasitic is considered below.)
Identity is a clear case -- so clear it could be a paradigm -- of an ontological relation that is
non-asymmetric and yet is used by physicalists (and
others) in contexts in which the lower-level
property P with which some higher-level property N is identical
nonetheless enjoys the priority;
N = P, yet P is prior to N. Even though
identity is non-asymmetric, the relation is used in
contexts in which the higher-level property is supposed to be asymmetrically dependent on the
lower-level property with which it is identical. Like remarks apply to relations of equivalence
between higher-level and lower-level properties, and thus to relations of property reduction that
amount to identity or equivalence.
What goes for identity and equivalence, in this
respect, goes for determination and
supervenience. An important part of the evidence for the assertion that P
determines/subvenes N
-- often the only evidence -- is an empirically adequate interlevel theory that connects the
P-phenomena with the N-phenomena.(27)
Even when the bridge principles of such a theory do not
take the form of or support assertions of identity (or of equivalence or any property reduction),
typically they do support assertions of determination/supervenience.(28)
Thus typically when a
higher-level N is determined/supervenient on certain lower-level properties
Pi -- which
determination/supervenience, being non-asymmetric, by itself entails no priority -- still the
lower-level Pi are
explanatorily prior to N by virtue of the role they play in an interlevel theory.
The priority involved is explanatory priority, and its source is the empirically adequate interlevel
theory on which the determination/supervenience claim is epistemically dependent. Given this
intimate epistemic tie between determination/supervenience and interlevel theories according to
which the lower-level properties are asymmetrically explanatorily prior, it is easy to understand
how the impression could arise, and the intuition become widespread, that determination and
supervenience themselves are asymmetric.
There is another way in which the
determination/supervenience claim typically depends on an
interlevel theory. Often we already have substantial observational evidence that N
is
determined/supervenient on the lower-level properties
Pi There remains a problem for the foregoing account of
how determination/supervenience can be
non-asymmetric even though it is the determination/supervenience base that enjoys explanatory
priority. So far we have only seen how the account works for determination/supervenience
between levels connected by an interlevel theory, as are biochemistry and cell biology. What
about determination/supervenience between levels not so connected?
They can fail to be connected in either of two ways.
One we've already seen, where the two
levels are connected not by an interlevel theory but by a chain of them; we'll return to this kind
of case in a moment. The other involves levels that by contrast are indeed near neighbors but as
yet there exists no interlevel theory to connect them. This was the case with thermodynamics
and particle mechanics before the development of a kinetic theory of temperature, the case with
genetics and biochemistry before the development of molecular genetics, and so on. These were
cases where as yet there was no empirically adequate interlevel theory on which an interlevel
determination/supervenience claim could be epistemically and explanatorily parasitic. And yet
in light of observational evidence even at the time, we might well want to assert, as some did
assert, that a particular higher-level property N is determined/supervenient on some
specific
lower-level Pi Very often, perhaps typically, when scientists
discover, observationally, that N is
determined/supervenient on Pi Even where no elaborately developed interlevel
theory is expected or hoped for, typically there
will be a general presumption, as much metaphysical as scientific (atomist, say, or materialist, or
naturalist), that the lower-level phenomena will in some sense explain the higher-level.(30) It
is
within some such general explanatory framework, metaphysical or otherwise, that the
determination/supervenience claim typically is made and from which the explanatory priority of
Pi
derives.
What about the case in which two levels are
connected by a chain of interlevel theories, as are
physics and psychology? No leapfrog interlevel theory exists that is both empirically adequate
and connects physics directly with psychology (except possibly for physical theories of quite
narrow subfields of psychology). Even if some such leapfrog were to be constructed, it would be
unlikely to satisfy (3)-(7) of §3 to the same extent as do the empirically adequate interlevel
theories that warrant assertions of determination/supervenience between near neighbors. The
hopeful leapfrog would be unlikely, therefore, to warrant the assertion of
determination/supervenience between physics and psychology. Yet physicalists want to say not
only that the physical determines/subvenes the psychological, but that the physical is
explanatorily prior to the psychological. How can they, in the absence of a suitable leapfrog
theory?
The physical need not be explanatorily prior to the
psychological in the same way a lower-level
F is explanatorily prior to a neighboring higher-level G when
F and G are connected by an
interlevel explanatory theory. Instead, physics can be explanatorily prior to psychology, and
indeed to any other (distant) higher-level science, by way of lying at the end of a certain chain of
sciences (or theories) between physics and the (distant) science, which sciences (or theories) are
connected pairwise by explanatory interlevel theories. The point is not to infer
from the chain of
pairwise interlevel explanations that there is an interlevel explanation of the
psychological by the
physical (via some leapfrog physical psychology). This would violate the non-transitivity of the
relevant notion(s) of explanation. Rather, given that each level in the chain is explanatorily prior
to the next higher level, we infer that the lowest level (physics) is explanatorily
prior to the
highest. Explanatory priority is transitive even when explanation is not.
Someone might reply(31)
that if explanatory priority is transitive, there could be no objection to an
in-virtue-of relation that (i) involves only this element of explanatory priority; (ii) is implied by
the determination/supervenience relation; and (iii) being asymmetric, induces asymmetry of the
determination that implies it. And it is true that the argument of §3 against an implied
in-virtue-of relation would not work here. That argument was aimed at an in-virtue-of relation
that obtains
when there is not only explanatory priority of the lower-level properties over the higher-level,
but an actual explanation of the latter by the former. Thus it is tempting to appeal to an implied
in-virtue-of relation that involves only explanatory priority, in order to conclude that
determination/supervenience must be asymmetric after all.
The reply ignores the substitutivity argument of §4,
according to which physicalist
determination/supervenience cannot be asymmetric. Granted the argument, there must be some
flaw in the reply. There is. If (i)-(iii) were to count as a sound argument for asymmetry of
determination/supervenience, a parallel argument could be constructed to show that identity too
is asymmetric, which is absurd. Here is the parallel: Identity, like determination and
supervenience, typically is asserted by physicalists in contexts in which the lower-level property
P with which the higher-level N is identical enjoys explanatory
priority because it is in virtue of
having P that something has N. So identity, like
determination/supervenience, carries with it an
implied in-virtue-of relation that involves an element of explanatory priority. Since the latter is
asymmetric, identity is asymmetric as well.
Obviously something has gone wrong. There is
nothing wrong with assumption (i) that there is
an in-virtue-of relation that involves only explanatory priority, and nothing wrong with
assumption (iii) that by being asymmetric, this in-virtue-of relation would induce asymmetry of
any relation that implies it. That leaves (ii), the assumption that the explanatory priority (or the
in-virtue-of relation that implies it) is implied by the identity relation, in the sense
that for any F
and G in its field, whenever F = G then F
is explanatorily prior to G. True, identity of G with F
typically is asserted by physicalists in contexts in which F is explanatorily prior to
G. But it is
asserted by them in other contexts as well, and it hardly follows that whenever F =
G, F is
explanatorily prior to G; contextual implication is not unmediated implication. The
identity can
(and often does) obtain even when there is no explanatory priority involved, as in same-level
cases like recursiveness = Markov computability, a farady = Avogadro's number of electron
charges, and so on.
Here then is another respect in which
determination/supervenience resembles identity: neither
implies a relation of explanatory priority (as opposed to contextually implying it). Physicalists
do typically assert determination/supervenience of G on F in contexts
in which F is explanatorily
prior to G. Nonetheless it can be true that F determines/subvenes
G even when F is not
explanatorily prior to G. For example, if temperature is both
determined/supervenient on and
identical with mean molecular kinetic energy, it follows by substitutivity that temperature
determines/subvenes mean molecular kinetic energy; yet temperature is not explanatorily prior to
mean molecular kinetic energy. And further like identity, determination/supervenience can
obtain whether or not there is a chain of interlevel theories, or even the hope of one, on which a
determination/supervenience claim could be evidentially and explanatorily
dependent.
Thus the transitivity of explanatory priority, contrary
to the reply, is no threat to the general
picture presented here of the asymmetry of the explanatory priority of the physical combined
with the non-asymmetry of determination/supervenience. The picture again is this. The
transitivity of determination/supervenience allows us to infer physical determination of the
distant higher-level phenomena from the pairwise determinations/supervenience between
intervening sciences that are near neighbors. These proximate pairwise
determinings/supervenings are in turn epistemically and explanatorily dependent on empirically
adequate interlevel theories. In this way the claim that the physical determines the distant
phenomena is epistemically and explanatorily dependent on an intervening chain of empirically
adequate interlevel theories. So far from being a premise for the physicalist, or a
metaphysical
brute fact, as some have charged,(32)
determination (along with global supervenience) is a hard-won empirical
conclusion wrestled from generations of interlevel theory-construction between
the sciences. Furthermore, the physical is explanatorily prior to the distant phenomena in the
sense that the physical lies at the end of some such explanatory chain.
Hence the asymmetric explanatory priority of the
physical -- or, equivalently, the explanatory
dependence of the nonphysical -- has its source not in some alleged asymmetry of
determination/supervenience, but elsewhere, in the asymmetry of the explanatory priority
involved in chains of interlevel theoretic explanations, on which chains our assertions of physical
determination/supervenience are epistemically and explanatorily dependent. Moreover, what
excludes the reverse determination/supervenience of the physical on the nonphysical is not the
physicalist's concept of determination/supervenience, including any alleged asymmetry, but the
world. What the chains of empirically adequate interlevel theories give us evidence of, among
other things, is what in the world determines/subvenes what. In particular, they give evidence
that while the physical determines/subvenes everything nonphysical, the reverse, as a matter of
empirical fact, does not happen.(33)
However, explanatory priority is not the only kind of
primacy the physical can enjoy over the
nonphysical. Nor need it be involved in one's notion of ontological primacy (and perhaps it
should not be). Until now I have argued only that if it is involved, the resulting asymmetry of
ontological primacy is entirely consistent with the non-asymmetry of
determination/supervenience. So let us consider, as promised, some other things that might be
meant by "ontological primacy."
Sometimes the physical is said to be prior in the sense
that it determines/subvenes everything
nonphysical but never vice versa. As noted toward the end of §3, this can make it look as though
determination/supervenience must be asymmetric. But as we also noted, the inference to
asymmetry is a non sequitur. We may rightly accord primacy to the physical, in
the sense that
the physical objectively determines/subvenes everything nonphysical but not vice versa, without
presupposing that determination/supervenience is asymmetric.
What else might be meant by 'ontological primacy'?
Suppose that an ontology is among other
things a theory of what it is to be.(34)
According to the physicalist theory, to be (anything at all) is
to be physical, in the sense that for any concrete thing, to be is to be (i) composed of entities of
the kind studied in physics, and (ii) in such a way that all the thing's properties are determined by
physical properties, not vice versa (ignoring abstracta, if any). So the claim that the physical
enjoys ontological primacy over the nonphysical might amount to the assertion simply of (i) and
(ii). But thesis (i) -- the composition thesis -- can be expressed, and explicated, without invoking
any determination relation, let alone an asymmetric one.(35)
The determination thesis (ii), as we've
been seeing, can likewise be expressed without presupposing asymmetry of determination. So
the physical can be asymmetrically ontologically prior to the nonphysical in the sense of (i) and
(ii) even though the determination relation asymmetric. Like remarks apply to
supervenience.
Another sense in which entities of kind
P might be ontologically prior to those of kind N is that
the latter could not exist if the former did not. But this sort of asymmetric ontological primacy is
captured by the composition thesis: if everything concrete is composed of the basic
physical
entities, then if the latter did not exist neither would the former; destroy what a concrete thing is
composed of and you destroy the thing. Furthermore, the basic physical entities could have
existed even if conditions in our universe had blocked the evolution of complex "nonphysical"
beings (those that have nonphysical properties) for the physical entities to compose. Since
composition can be explicated without determination, asymmetric ontological primacy is again
consistent with non-asymmetric determination; so too for supervenience.
Some physicalists who talk of the ontological
primacy of the physical seem to mean (i) and (ii)
combined with an explanatory thesis (which may be to re-introduce a pragmatic/epistemic
notion, depending on one's theory of explanation). The primacy of the physical consists in
everything's being composed of the physical entities in such a way that the physical properties
not only determine/subvene but are explanatorily prior to the nonphysical properties. But we've
lately been seeing how and in what sense the physical properties can be explanatorily prior to the
nonphysical, via chains of empirically adequate interlevel theories, and how this explanatory
primacy of the physical, plus the corresponding dependence of the nonphysical, can be
understood without asymmetry of determination/supervenience.
Finally, note that for each of the foregoing senses of ontological primacy, the assertion
merely that the physical determines/subvenes the nonphysical is not meant, by itself, to capture
or express ontological primacy in that sense, but at most only in conjunction with further if
closely related matters. It is partly for this reason, in addition to the reasons given above, that for
each of these senses there is a positive account of primacy in that sense which implies no
asymmetry of determinational dependence or of supervenience. Unless someone offers a further
sense of primacy that might imply the alleged asymmetry, arguments from the primacy of the
physical to the would-be asymmetry of determination/supervenience are a poor bet. And aside
from troubles with arguments for asymmetry, there would remain the substitutivity argument of
§4 against it. It follows that explications of determination and supervenience, including those
according to which they are nonreductive and/or global, cannot be faulted for failing to entail
asymmetry. To the contrary, the fault would seem to lie with explications that require it.
1. Kim (1984), 162.
2. Kim (1990), 13; Kim (1984), 166. Kim has plenty of
company in assuming asymmetry, including Petrie (1987), 127; Grimes (1988), 157; DePaul
(1987), 433, 438; Miller (1990), 695-696; Papineau (1990), 67; Poland (1994), §1.2, 2.3. One
also hears the assumption frequently in conversation.
3. Hellman and Thompson (1975), (1977); Horgan (1982),
(1984); Lewis (1983); Post (1987), Ch. 4; Post (1991), Chs. 5-6, Post (1995). None of these
explications entails asymmetry of determination.
4. Kim (1990), 25.
5. Kim (1990), 25-27. Cf. Kim (1987), 321-322, and Kim
(1989), 42, on the need for specific "local determinations."
6. Kim (1990), 14-15.
7. Kim (1990), 16.
8. Kim (1990), 16.
9. Kim (1990), 16. Others who assume an implied in-virtue-of
relation include DePaul (1987), 430; Grimes (1988), 156 (D); Poland (1994), §1.2, 2.3.
10. Kim (1984), 175.
11. Kim (1984), 175.
12. Kim (1990), 9.
13. Kim (1990), 24.
14. The following account draws on the more detailed one in
Post (1987), Ch. 5, and Post (1991), Ch. 6. See also Kincaid (1990).
15. Post (1987), 216, 221.
16. Leapfrog approaches like Papineau's (1990), which would
deduce physical determination of the mental from "the completeness of physics," do not explain
why anyone in doubt about the physical determination of the mental should believe the intended
"completeness" of physics. Cf. Crane (1991), 34.
17. Outline proof: Assume that (i) (x,y)(Rxy --> Qxy),
and (ii) (ExEyEz)((Rxy & Ryz) & -Qxz) -- say Rab & Rbc but not Qac. It follows
by US and tautological inference that (Rab & Rbc) & -Rac, which entails
not-(x)(y)(z)((Rxy & Ryz) --> Rxz), which means R is not transitive.
18. The case in which what is implied is a relation not of
explanation but only of explanatory priority is considered in §5.
19. Post (1997), §4; Post and Turner (2000).
20. Cf. Lehrer (1970), 122-123; Jaeger (1975), 482-484; Klein
(1976), 806-807; Post (1980), 39-40. Neander and Menzies (1990), 464-465, give related
reasons for rejecting transitivity of causal explanation in certain cases.
21. (1)-(7) are drawn from the more detailed account in
Kincaid (1990), who draws in turn on Darden and Maull (1977), Maull (1977), and Kitcher
(1984). Interlevel theories are an especially important kind of "connective theory" discussed in
Post (1987), §5.1.
22. As suggested by Post (1987), 227-228.
23. Cf. Petrie (1987), 127; Grimes (1988), 157; DePaul (1987),
433, 438; Miller (1990), 695-696; Papineau (1990), 67; Poland (forthcoming), §1.2, 2.3.
24. Churchland (1985), 14.
25. As in effect does Kim (1990), 25-26.
26. As someone has, though not for attribution.
27. Post (1987), 217.
28. Post (1987), §5.1, and Post (1991), 103-139. Cf. Kincaid
(1988), (1990).
29. Post (1991), 109-130. Cf. Post (1987), §5.1. Melnyk
(1991), 578, among others, overlooks this sort of reply, further elaborated below, to the demand
to know "what accounts for [the] assertability" of determination.
30. Hooker (1987), 112-113, 122, 131.
31. As someone has, though not for attribution.
32. Kim (1990), 24-27; Melnyk (1991); Schiffer (1987),
153-154. The remark in Post (1987), 187, that physical determination might be an ultimate fact
about the world that neither has nor requires explanation, has to do with a separate issue, namely
what to say about the cosmic question, 'Why, when it could have been otherwise, is ours a
physically determined world in the first place?' -- a question I there argue is in the much same
boat as 'Why is there a world at all?'
33. Post (1987), §5.1, 329.
34. Benardete (1989), Chs. 1-3; Post (1991), Ch. 1.
35. Hellman and Thompson (1975); Post (1987), 120-125,
166-173.
Benardete, Jose (1989). Metaphysics:
The Logical Approach (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Churchland, Paul M. (1985). "Reduction,
Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States," The
Journal of Philosophy, 77: 8-28.
Crane, Tim (1991). "Why Indeed? Papineau
on Supervenience," Analysis, 51: 32-37.
Darden, Lindley, and Maull, Nancy (1977).
"Interfield Theories," Philosophy of Science, 44: 43-64.
DePaul, Michael R. (1987). "Supervenience
and Moral Dependence," Philosophical Studies, 51:
425-439.
Grimes, Thomas R. (1988). "The Myth of
Supervenience," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 69:
152-160.
Hellman, Geoffrey, and Thompson, F. W.
(1975). "Physicalism, Ontology, Determination,
Reduction," The Journal of Philosophy, 72: 551-564.
Hellman, Geoffrey, and Thompson, F. W.
(1977). "Physicalist Materialism," Nous, 11: 309-345.
Hooker, C. A. (1987). A Realistic
Theory of Science (Albany: State University of New York Press).
Horgan, Terence (1982). "Supervenience
and Microphysics," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63:
29-43.
Horgan, Terence (1984). "Supervenience
and Cosmic Hermeneutics," Southern Journal of
Philosophy, 22, Supplement: 19-38.
Jaeger, Robert A. (1975). "Implication and
Evidence," The Journal of Philosophy, 72: 475-485.
Kim, Jaegwon (1984). "Concepts of
Supervenience," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,
45: 153-176.
Kim, Jaegwon (1987). " 'Strong' and 'Global'
Supervenience Revisited," Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 48: 315-326.
Kim, Jaegwon (1989). "The Myth of
Nonreductive Materialism," Proceedings and Addresses of the
American Philosophical Association, 33: 31-47.
Kim, Jaegwon (1990). "Supervenience as a
Philosophical Concept," Metaphilosophy, 21: 1-27.
Kincaid, Harold (1988). "Supervenience and
Explanation," Synthese, 77: 251-281.
Kincaid, Harold (1990). "Molecular Biology
and the Unity of Science," Philosophy of Science, 57:
575-593.
Kitcher, Philip (1984). "1953 and All That.
A Tale of Two Sciences," The Philosophical Review,
43: 335-374.
Klein, Peter D. (1976). "Knowledge,
Causality, and Defeasibility," The Journal of Philosophy, 73:
792-812.
Lehrer, Keith (1970). "Justification,
Explanation, and Induction," in Marshal Swain, ed., Induction,
Acceptance and Rational Belief (Dordrecht: Reidel), 100-133.
Lewis, David (1983). "New Work for a
Theory of Universals," Australasian Journal of Philosophy,
61: 343-377.
Maull, Nancy (1977). "Unifying Science
Without Reduction," Studies in the History and
Philosophy of Science, 9: 143-162.
Melnyk, Andrew (1991). "Physicalism:
From Supervenience to Elimination," Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 51, 573-587.
Miller, Richard B. (1990). "Supervenience
is a Two-way Street," The Journal of Philosophy, 87:
695-701.
Neander, Karen, and Menzies, Peter (1990).
"David Owens on Levels of Explanation," Mind, 99,
459-466.
Papineau, David (1990). "Why
Supervenience?" Analysis, 50: 66-70.
Petrie, Bradford (1987). "Global
Supervenience and Reduction," Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 48: 119-130.
Poland, Jeffrey (1994). Physicalism:
The Philosophical Foundations (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Post, John F. (1980). "Infinite Regresses of
Justification and of Explanation," Philosophical Studies,
38: 31-52.
Post, John F. (1987). The
Faces of
Existence: An Essay in Nonreductive Metaphysics (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press)
Post, John F. (1991). Metaphysics: A
Contemporary Introduction (New York: Paragon House)
Post, John F. (1995). " 'Global'
Supervenient Determination: Too Permissive?" in Essays on
Supervenience, ed. Elias Savellos and mit Yalçin (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press,
1995), 73-100."
Post, John F. (1997). "Regress, Transitivity, and Terminal Philosophy," available by request.
Post, John F. (forthcoming). "Counterexamples and Physical Supervenient Determination."
Post, John F., and Turner, Derek (2000). "Sic Transitivity: Reply to McGrew
and McGrew," The Journal of Philosophical Research,
25, 67-82.
Schiffer, Stephen R. (1987). Remnants of Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
Footnotes
References